![]() Healthcare Training Institute - Quality Education since 1979 CE for Psychologist, Social Worker, Counselor, & MFT!!
Section 19 Question 19 | Answer Booklet | Table of Contents
In the early Christian era the excessive martyrdom and penchant toward suicide of early believers frightened church elders sufficiently for them to introduce a serious deterrent. That constraint was to relate suicide to crime and to the sin associated with that crime. A major change occurred in the 4th century with a categorical rejection of suicide by St. Augustine (3 54-430). Suicide was considered a crime because it precluded the possibility of repentance and because it violated the biblical Sixth Commandment relating to killing. Suicide was a greater sin than any sin one might wish to avoid. This view was elaborated by St. Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274), who emphasized that suicide was a mortal sin in that it usurped God's power over man's life and death. Neither the Old nor the New Testament directly forbids suicide, but by the year 700 the Catholic Church proclaimed that a person who attempted suicide was to be excommunicated. The notion of suicide as sin took firm hold and for hundreds of years thereafter played an important part in the Western view of self-destruction. There is much to learn about the long stretch of several hundred years from 1000 A.D. to the 18th century, and much of it is explicated in the French historian and scholar Georges Minois's scholarly book entitled History of Suicide (1996). That book provides us with a segue to the French philosopher Jean Jacques Rousseau (1712-1778) who, by emphasizing the natural state of man, transferred sin from man to society, making people generally good and asserting that society makes them bad. The disputation as to the locus of blame-whether in people or in society-is a major tension that resonates throughout the history of suicidal thought. David Hume (1711-1776) was one of the first major Western philosophers to discuss suicide in the absence of the concept of sin. His famous essay "On Suicide," published in 1777, the year after his death, was promptly suppressed. That well-reasoned essay is a statement of the Enlightenment's position on suicide. The burden of the essay is to refute the view that suicide is a crime; it does so by arguing that suicide is not a transgression of our duties to God or to our fellow citizens or to ourselves. Hume states that prudence and courage should engage us to rid ourselves at once of existence when it becomes a burden. . . . If it be no crime in me to divert the Nile or Danube from its course, were I able to effect such purposes, where then is the crime in turning a few ounces of blood from their natural channel? Whereas Hume tried to decriminalize suicide, Rousseau turned the blame from man to society. In the 20th century, the two giants of suicidal theorizing-Emile Durkheim (1858-1917) in France and Sigmund Freud (1856-1939) in Austria-played rather different roles: Durkheim focused on society's inimical effects on the individual, while Freud, eschewing both the notions of sin and of crime, gave suicide back to man but put the locus of action in our unconscious mind. Durkheim's best-known work Le Suicide in 1897 (although unavailable in English until 1951) established a model for sociological investigation of suicide. There have been many subsequent studies of this genre. The monographs and books on suicide by Ruth Cavan (Chicago, 1926), Calvin Schmidt (Seattle, 1928), Peter Sainsbury (London, 1955), and Henry and Short (business cycles, 1954) all fall within the tradition of taking a plot of ground-a city or a country-and figuratively or literally reproducing its map several times to show its socially shady (and topographically shaded) areas, and their differential relationships to suicide rates. According to Durkheim, suicide is the result of society's strength or weakness of control over the individual. He posited three basic types of suicide, each a result of our relationship to society. In one instance, the "altruistic" suicide is literally required by that individual's society. Here, the customs or rules of the group demand suicide under certain circumstances. Harakin and suttee are examples of altruistic suicide. In such instances, the person acted as though he had little choice. Self-inflicted death was honorable; continuing to live was ignominious. Society dictated a person's actions, and as individuals we are not strong enough to defy custom. Most suicides in the United States are "egoistic"-Durkheim's second category. Contrary to the circumstances of an altruistic suicide, egoistic suicide occurs when the individual has too few ties with his or her community. Demands-in this case, to live-do not reach him or her. Proportionately, more unconnected individuals, especially men who are on their own-lonely old men-kill themselves than do people who are connected to church or family. Finally, Durkheim called "anomic" those suicides that occurred when the accustomed relationship between an individual and society is suddenly shattered or disrupted. The shocking, immediate loss of a job or the death of a close friend or the loss of a fortune is thought sufficient to precipitate anomic suicide or, conversely, poor men surprised by sudden wealth have been shocked into anomic suicide. A situation of estrangement to one's usual ties to the habitual aspects of one's society is called anomie. The students and followers of Durkheim include Maurice Halbwachs in France and Ronald Mans and Jack D. Douglas in the United States. Douglas, especially, argued that Durkheim's constructs came not so much from the facts of life and death as from official statistics that may have distorted those very facts that they are purported to report. As Durkheim detailed the sociology of suicide, so Freud (although not writing directly on this topic) fathered psychological explanations. To him, suicide was essentially in the mind. Because individuals ambivalently identify with the objects of their own love, when they are frustrated the aggressive side of the ambivalence turns itself against the internalized person. The main psychoanalytical position on suicide was that it represented unconscious hostility directed toward the introjected ambivalently viewed love objects. For example, one killed oneself to murder the image of one's loved-hated father within one's breast. Psychodynamically, suicide was seen as murder in the 180th degree. Contemporary psychoanalysis has modified this view in a number of ways that extend the confines of this original prescription. In an important exegesis of suicide, Robert E. Litman (1921- ) traced the development of Freud's thoughts on this subject, taking into account Freud's clinical experiences and his changing theoretical positions from 1881 to 1939. It is evident from Litman's analysis that there are more factors to the psychodynamics of suicide than hostility. These factors include the general features of the human condition in Western civilization, specifically suicide-prone mechanisms involving rage, guilt, anxiety, dependency, and a great number of predisposing conditions. The feelings of helplessness, hopelessness, and abandonment are very important. Psychodynamic explanations
of suicide theory did not change too much from Freud to the American psychiatrist
Karl Menninger (1893- 1990). In his important 1938 book, Man Against Himself,
Menninger, in captivating ordinary language, delineated the psychodynamics of
hostility and asserted that the hostile drive in suicide is made up of three skeins:
the wish to kill, the wish to be killed, and the wish to die. Gregory Zilboorg
(1890-1959) refined this psychoanalytic hypothesis and stated that every suicidal
case contained strong, unconscious hostility combined with an unusual lack of
capacity to love others. He extended the locus of concern from solely intrapsychic
dynamics to the external world and maintained that the role of a broken home in
suicidal proneness demonstrated that both intrapsychic and external etiological
elements were present. There is yet another contemporary thread; it comes from the laboratory and has aspirations of being applicable in the clinic. It focuses both on the living and the dead brain and on such bodily fluids as blood and cerebrospinal fluid. It relates to the anatomy and physiology of suicide- the biological approach to the understanding of specific human behaviors. The
locus of conceptualization of suicide is set by the church, the government, books,
mores, society, writers, and leading-edge intellectuals. It reflects the zeitgeist:
the commonly held beliefs that are "in the air." Looking at this panorama
of ideas and sentiments over the past millennium, it seems to me that a number
of ideas have occupied intellectual space on the topic of suicide. Alliteratively,
I call them sin, sacrilege, socius, soma, serum, psyche, and selfhood. Over the
past 200 years, the main emphasis (and locus) for suicide has moved from accusations
of sin toward efforts at compassion, understanding, and prevention. The Encyclopedia
Britannica reflects these changes. My recent study2 of the 14 separate articles
on suicide in the various editions of the Encyclopaedia since 1777 (see the Epilogue)
showed that society has moved light-years since the 18th-century excoriation of
suicide as cowardly, sinful, and shameful to a contemporary emphasis on nurturance
and support-like the Samaritans in Great Britain and the suicide prevention and
hotline activities in the United States, whose interactions often begin with the
question "How can we help you?" QUESTION
19 |